THERE ARE NEIGHBOURS AND THEN THERE ARE NEIGHBOURS: WHEN
SHOULD A JUDGE NOT JUDGE THE POLICE FOR NOT POLICING?
AG v
TIO[*] and TIO v BEENGO
et al [**]
IAN FRASER[1]
INTRODUCTIONThis is a Comment on a case decided
by the High Court and Court of Appeal of Kiribati, in the winter of 2003. It
concerns a small jurisdiction, and it occurred some time ago, but the subject
was the question posed in the Comment’s title and for several reasons,
among them the jurisdiction and the date, this is a subject of some interest,
perhaps soon of some lively interest, to anyone involved with the law of the
South Pacific – in the courts and in the streets and villages. For it
concerns not only the relations between our judges and our police but those
among our judges, and between them and their brethren abroad.
THE FLOW
OF LAW, AND A CITE UNSEENOne of the features of the common law that
makes it a complex legacy for the South Pacific insular jurisdictions is its
sensitivity to local conditions and values. This is a feature not necessarily of
its actual responsiveness to society, on which opinion must vary, so much as of
its permitted, even necessary,
logic, declared by its stewards and
authors. In the application of the common law to a dispute it is always a
legitimate argument that a potential ruling does not accord with local
conditions, or norms and values; and for a great many common-law rules the
perceived demand of the local community is the entire justification, the very
foundation.
That community is, in the law’s origins, English; and in
the law’s ongoing development as received in the Pacific, it is
overwhelmingly British and Australasian. British
or Australasian, rather;
this very sensitivity has generated a series of divurgences in common-law
doctrines between Australia and the UK, and even between Australia and New
Zealand. As decisions accumulate on a novel issue, or a new extension of the
law, or in the adjustment of a traditional doctrine, the jurisdictions are alert
to the directions taken within each other, but the path finally taken is the one
local courts assert to be most appropriate to local societies.
This process
depends on two resources that are scant or even absent in the insular
jurisdictions of the Pacific: judges confident of their appreciation
of
local conditions and values; and litigants in the abundance required by a law
that relies on the reiteration and variation of concrete cases. So it cannot
proceed as naturally, at least, in the Pacific as in its home societies. Yet
Pacific constitutions require that local judge-made law take inspiration
(sometimes primary inspiration) from English common
law.
[2] And that allows a
manageable role to Pacific courts. In the areas of law where all paths are
foreign, courts here maintain fidelity to their constitutional responsibility,
in effect, by locating the legitimacy of their rulings in the constituting
legislature’s choice of foreign law as a main source of non-statutory law.
Within that foreign law, the common law of English-descended societies,
legitimacy derives rather from asserted congruence with social norms and values;
here, where that law is extended to the islands, legitimacy is a positivistic
derivation from the constitutions.
Perhaps the parole rule of contracts
suits Melanesian needs as well as it does English needs, perhaps it does not;
but in any event Melanesian constitutions direct their courts to take the
English path where legislatures have failed to make the law, and so the courts
do. The rule, after all, flows naturally enough from contract principle, and
beyond doubt the constitution adopts such principles. In torts perhaps the fault
principle suits Pacific societies, perhaps it does not, but again it is
naturally inherent to the English principles of civil responsibility explicitly
adopted by the constitutions. A judge can in good faith assume its
appropriateness by relying on legislative supremacy, rather than on the
doctrine’s original basis in community standards.
Thus the rules of
common law developed in other contexts, by principles originating in other
societies, flow with apparent ease through Pacific law, despite the adopted
common law’s own nature. You do not need a local precedent to know that a
suit in false imprisonment will require proof of total confinement rather than
mere obstruction, or that one in negligence claiming a novel duty of care will
turn on foreseeability of injury and proximity between the parties.
But
this Kiribati case,
Tio v Beengo et al and its appeal
A-G v Tio,
is such a case, a claim to a novel duty of care in negligence. The judges indeed
were concerned with foreseeability and proximity, as these terms are used in
English precedents. Why need we lead with a disquisition on the jurisprudential
basis of Pacific common law?
Because some common-law rules are
not
based on principle. The principles of the common law are based on social
conditions and norms, as the judges have seen these, but some rules are not even
said to be based on principle, the principles adopted by the constitutions. They
are, rather, said to be the result of policy choices: choices that English or
Australian or New Zealand judges have made in explicit isolation from their
law’s principles. These rules, instead, are based directly on the
particular social context of their application. They are not formalisations of
cultural precepts found in local society, but exercises in direct social
engineering. For a Pacific court, therefore, legitimacy in applying these rules
is not available from the constitutional injunction to base the local law on the
principles of English common law.
And the novel duty in negligence claimed
by Mr Tio was a duty to take care in protecting him and his interests from
criminal acts by third parties, a duty owed to him by the Kiribati police. In
English common law, such a claim encounters ‘the
Hill
immunity’, a rule denying a duty of care in police forces and officers
concerning ‘the investigation and suppression of
crime’.
[3] It is based
explicitly on policy concerns relating to policing in England, a rule
self-consciously formulated and applied as an exception to principle. Depending
on how a judge construes the facts of Tio’s case, his or her decision must
include a decision on whether to apply this ‘immunity’ – and
to do that, he or she must proceed from the norms, values, and conditions of
Kiribati, just as did the English courts from those of the UK.
Now, there
are other such policy-based rules in the common law(s), even others within the
tort of negligence. Notably there is the English formula limiting liability for
psychological harm suffered by people affected by injury done to third parties
by defendants, which is acknowledged even in application to be unsatisfactory
yet is maintained in the name of ‘policy’ – and has recently
been rejected for Australia by the High
Court.
[4] There is, too, another
negligence immunity, that of advocates toward their clients, which has recently
been abandoned in England and maintained in Australia in decisions turning
almost entirely on
‘policy’.
[5] Why focus on
the policy rule concerning police immunity?
Because the salience in the
South Pacific of psychological-injury negligence claims by ‘secondary
victims’ and of malpractice suits against lawyers for their court work is,
so far, largely theoretical. Such claims will emerge sometime, no doubt. But
claims in negligence against the police, concerning their work in investigating
and suppressing crime, have already emerged. Tio’s case does not stand
alone. Indeed on an insular scale we could say such claims are proliferating;
there have been at least five in this century, in Fiji, Tonga, and Kiribati, all
but one to appellate level.
[6]
Moreover this tide flows in Australia too, where (apart from
Tame,
mentioned above) there were at least three cases in 2004 and 2005 raising
‘the English immunity’ of police
operations.
[7] England itself has seen
Hill challenged and qualified repeatedly since the decision’s
issue, including three appeals to the Law Lords this
century.
[8] The doctrine’s
status is undecided, indeed contested, in Australia, as common law. In England
its status as common law is secure, albeit qualified since
Hill, but the
implementation of the European Convention on Human Rights leaves it just as
contestable as in Australia, as
law.
[9] So Tio’s case
participates in an interesting wider set of developments in the common law,
including a movement within the South Pacific. But
A-G v Tio was decided
in August 2003, almost three years ago at the present writing. Since then, just
within the region, there have been two other appellate decisions on the police
immunity. Why devote a Case Comment to Tio’s case now?
Because it is
not really a movement, the set of South Pacific cases dealing with police
immunity in negligence. The issue is clearly acquiring prominence, attracting
plaintiffs and appeals – but the cases are handled one at a time. They do
not form a ‘line’ of cases in the common-law sense, for an awareness
of the others is in the observer only: not in the judicial opinions.
The
Court of Appeal of Fiji has heard and decided two cases since
A-G v Tio
in which a police immunity has been asserted and denied by the two sides, the
court ruling on the issue in both cases; yet
Tio was not cited in either
one. But then, in
Tio itself, earlier Fiji cases on point were not cited.
Nor was an earlier decision on point of the Tongan Court of Appeal. In fact,
none of these decisions cited any one of the others: not across
jurisdictions, and not even within
Fiji.
[10] Case law was considered,
indeed relied on, in every judgment, but in every judgment it was case law from
the English and Australian
jurisdictions.
[11] So there
seems to be a role for academic discussion of this line of cases that
isn’t a line – neighbours not of one
lain, in the Tok Pisin
sense – and Tio’s case is a suitable one to focus on. Its age is a
reason to discuss it now, given its status, like the others, of precedent lost.
Moreover, it was decided, at trial and on appeal, in ways that expose more
clearly than the other cases both the police immunity issue and the deeper
problem of whether and how to adopt policy-based common-law
rules.
TRIAL: SIMPLY NEIGHBOURSIn November of 1999 two
police officers on Butaritai, a Kiribati island, learned that men of the
island’s village had resolved to punish a man, Tio, for reasons never
advanced in court. They advised Tio to leave his house by 6 pm that day;
otherwise ‘anything may happen to you’. When he asked whether they
would look after his house if he did, they said they were not sure but would ask
their superior, the other police officer on Butaritai. On the way back from his
house to their station they told the villagers (assembled for another purpose)
not to damage the house, but otherwise, they did nothing about the matter, then
or later. That evening, villagers smashed up Tio’s boat and stole his
fishing equipment. Tio watched from another house where he had taken
refuge.
Tio sued some of the villagers, the three police officers, and the
A-G as representative of the police force. (The villagers never appeared, and
Tio obtained a default judgment against them.) The officers and the A-G advanced
the immunity declared by
Hill v Chief Constable of West Yorkshire, with
the English progeny usually cited with
Hill.
[12] At the trial,
reported as
Tio v Beengo, Millhouse CJ put the question to himself
squarely: ‘Should I, must I, follow in Kiribati
Hill?’
[13] Of all the Pacific decisions
touching on police liability in negligence, this is the only one to pose and
answer the question of whether to adopt the
Hill
immunity.
Hill may be the English common law, he held, but it lacked
firm endorsement in the case law of Australia and New Zealand, and in Canada it
was explicitly rejected.
[14]
Millhouse CJ concluded that he was not constrained by sheer authority. He was
free to consider the
Hill doctrine on its merits, which is to say on its
policy suppositions. And the policy considerations applicable in Britain did not
apply in Kiribati.
Why not? His explanation is a little vague, but it does
clearly turn on a distinction: ‘English society is sophisticated and
complex: Kiribati society is, thankfully, comparatively unsophisticated and
simple.’ Kiribati is simply simpler than the UK.
Now, this could be a
matter of sheer scale – a jurisdiction like the Western Isles of Scotland
in comparison with the British jurisdiction of the House of Lords. Or it could
be the nature of crime and crime investigation and suppression
in this
small land. Millhouse CJ did specify that as a consequence of this distinction,
police liability in Kiribati would not produce the ‘unfortunate
consequences’ that it would in the larger country, consequences which
generated the policy concerns animating the decision in
Hill to create
the immunity.
This point might be a reference to the likelihood of a
‘flood’ of cases, the product of a population’s sophistication
and its size. It does seem reasonable to suppose that negligence floodgates are
under more pressure in the UK than in Kiribati.
But the main
point seems not to be that, and indeed
Hill does not mention the
floodgates argument as such. The main point seems rather to be that the kinds of
policing
decisions negligence suits would put in issue would be easier to
evaluate, in Kiribati, without disrupting proper police discretion. Tio’s
case, Millhouse CJ holds, is ‘a good example: what the police officers
did, did not do, and should have done, are plain’. The English cases are
not like this one, he observes. Again he does not say why, but the implication
must be that they concern debateable choices and more complex issues of policing
philosophy and policy, issues that the House of Lords in
Hill regarded as
unsuitable for judicial evaluation.
The sort of errors for which the
Kiribati police could expect to be sued, that is, would tend to be
straightforward, and easy to evaluate for negligence, whereas those for which
English forces could expect suits must tend to be complex and subtle. Litigation
concerning the simple Kiribati-style carelessness would not involve searching
inquiries into the details of past investigations, nor would the prospect of
liability foster a defensiveness in the finer points of detective work.
Superficial accounts in court of police foul-ups would suffice, the errors being
so evident, and any chilling effect – the ‘detrimentally defensive
frame of mind’ the Lords were anxious to avoid creating in police officers
– would extend only to fostering elementary competence and good faith.
Tio was a ‘good example’. In it the negligence lay in
simply failing to do anything after learning that villagers were planning crimes
against Tio, in an incident whose relevant facts occurred in the course of a
single day. And truly, few accounts of the sophisticated ways English forces
have been alleged to be negligent can be related so succinctly.
So the
public policy immunity is unnecessary. The case falls to be decided as a
straightforward instance of defendants just failing to make any effort to do
their plain duty. The duty appears
so plain that Millhouse CJ,
reasonably, does not pause to record rulings on the usual elements of a duty of
care: foreseeability of injury, obviously met on the facts, proximity between
the parties, which likewise could seem plain given the direct contact between
them concerning the very injury that occurred (and the role of police
generally), and whether a duty would be reasonable and fair, qualities
apparently subsumed in finding the duty, overall, to be
‘plain’.
[15] It does
seem otiose to bother with such a ‘test’, with such
‘factors’, in a situation so clearly covered by Lord Atkin’s
commandment in
Donoghue v Stevenson [1932] AC 562 not to injure thy
neighbour, by action or inaction, a ‘neighbour’ being anyone
‘so closely and directly affected by my act that I ought to have them in
my contemplation’.
A simple case, in a simple land. Now, what makes a
case simple, generally, is the omission of facts. Millhouse CJ was subjected to
that by the parties’ choices, in particular the defendant police
force’s choice, not to lead evidence answering the obvious questions.
There was no evidence as to why the police officers stayed away from
Tio’s house, or what might have happened if they had attempted to stop the
villagers, or how the villagers responded to the officers’ attempt to
dissuade them, or what resources were available to the force as a whole. There
was no account of what they were doing, or expected to be doing, that evening.
There was no evidence about why the villagers were upset with Tio in the first
place, or about such incidents occurring elsewhere in Kiribati. The court did
not know whether any of the police came from this island. There was not any
evidence about what, if anything, police had done subsequently about prosecuting
the men who trashed Tio’s property.
We can, therefore, picture the
situation as Millhouse CJ did. We can agree that ‘[i]t would be
interesting, but not necessary, to know the background...’ Police officers
are aware of a serious crime about to be committed, nearby, including the
precise location and identities of the victim and the perpetrators, and they
ignore it without explanation. Duty is ‘plain’, and in the absence
of evidence to show that what looks like dereliction of duty was not truly just
that, he held them to the simplest of professional standards (‘Not good
policing.’). Breach thus being clear, he awarded damages.
As his last
comment, on liability, he remarked that the police conduct here was
‘morally indefensible’; it was a satisfaction to make it legally
actionable too.
APPEAL: NEIGHBOURHOOD MUST BE ASSUMEDThe
Court of Appeal – Hardie Boys, Tomkins, and Pennington JJA, in a single
opinion – approached the case very differently, and not so simply. The
issue of a duty’s existence should be dealt with first, they held, before
considering the
Hill immunity. And on these facts a duty is not plain at
all.
Indeed what is missing is neighbourhood: ‘what has variously been
described as ‘proximity of relationship’ and
‘neighbourhood’’. In a line of English cases before and after
Hill where proximity was held to exist between police forces (or prison
services) and members of the public (or individual police officers), they found
the common element to be the creation of the risk, from whose realisation the
plaintiff suffered,
by police officers (or prison guards). It is the
creation of such a risk by defendant which, in police cases, establishes the
special relationship necessary to a duty of care.
So Tio’s case was
like
Alexandrou,
[16] one of
the English cases where proximity was held not to exist (and cited, unlike the
others, in Millhouse CJ’s judgment). There the only link between the
plaintiff and the police was an automatic burglar alarm, calling them from his
store.
Then the CA adds that the Butaritai police never did undertake to
look after Tio’s property. Such an ‘assumption of
responsibility’, they imply, supported by some of the English cases, could
have established proximity between the police and
Tio.
[17] Without the assumed
responsibility, and in a case where the injury did not result from police fault
– although at the outset of the opinion they remark that they make no
comment on causation, since it was not discussed at trial – there can be
no duty of care. The police conduct here, they agree with Millhouse CJ, was
‘morally indefensible’; but it could not be a breach of a negligence
duty to Tio.
And since there is no duty on these general principles, there
is no need even to remark upon the immunity
from duty created by
Hill, or on Millhouse CJ’s ‘robust view’ of its
applicability to Kiribati.
PRECEDENTThe basis of the trial
decision not having been ruled or even commented on by the appeal decision,
Tio’s case is effectively two precedents: one, Millhouse CJ’s, on
the
Hill immunity, and another, the CA’s reversing him, on
proximity in police cases. Each is significant in several ways, like any
decision in an area of ‘developing’ law, but each has one feature
that seems of particular importance, to Kiribati and to the
region.
There goes this neighbourhood: Millhouse CJ’s
decisionOne can question the soundness of Millhouse CJ’s
distinction between simple cases and complex ones as applied so sweepingly to
Kiribati, or indeed as applied to the facts of this case. What made the
statement of facts so simple was the paucity
of fact. In reality, the
police must have had reasons for not interfering with the villagers, and the
villagers reasons, perhaps related, for their hostility to Tio.
More
importantly, this would not necessarily be just a
dispute, such as might
arise in an English village. Indeed it almost certainly was not anything like
that, for English villages participate in a formal system of government with
some effective reach into each street, so that any such ganging-up of people
against one person, however popular, would have to be in flat contravention of
every applicable law. These facts transposed to an English, or Australian,
village, would indeed be seen legally as a simple case, the law of government
and crimes displacing the sociological complexities to produce a space of
simplicity for the operation of the law of negligence.
But the people who
trashed Tio’s property, it is clear enough from the facts found, were
representing the village. They held no formal office and were exercising no
statutory powers – but if they were representing the village, that is a
council of ‘old men’ of the village, they were
acting as the
village government. For Kiribati recognises custom as a source of law, and
by Kiribati custom such old men (the
unimane, a council made up of an
elder from each household) are the authority of the village. Day to day, this is
how rural Kiribati is governed, and to the extent it is sanctioned by the
Constitution, this authority is lawful. It co-exists with the police stationed
on the many islands, but it is the only local political
authority.
[18] Now the
unimane enforce their decisions, when necessary, by customary means
– which include a form of banishment. This is executed by ordering the
offending person or people to evacuate their home by 6 pm, after which some
degree of damage or theft of their property (or some degree of personal violence
if the offender has not left) constitutes an aspect of the punishment. It seems,
of course, likely enough on a balance of probabilities that precisely this is
what happened to Tio.
[19] This
is a rather untidy procedure, and the risk of abuse (however ‘abuse’
would be gauged) seems high. But that is not the point here, except insofar as
it highlights the uncertainty of evaluating the legality of a given exercise of
the procedure. It is indubitably custom, and custom is indubitably a source of
law in Kiribati. The legitimate extent of this customary jurisdiction is
controversial, as of course must be any particular exercise of it, including
this one – for there are, of course, other norms in the Constitution,
including a bill of rights in orthodox terms, and Kiribati has not even
formalised the authority of the
unimane in a statute whose terms could be
fairly readily set against the Constitution (as Samoa has done with the
unimane’s cultural predecessor, the village
fono[20]). So no-one can say
with certainty whether the attack on Tio was a lawful exercise of customary
authority, or an abuse of authority otherwise lawful, or indeed legally nothing
more than a mob attack. The basic binary distinction of the law, between lawful
and unlawful, which grounds the legitimacy of police power, is made fuzzy by the
nature of Kiribati’s conceptually fuzzy legal regime. (In part, this is a
consequence of the shortage of litigants already remarked.) Apart from the fact
that Tio apparently showed no surprise at the news of the impending attack,
which proves nothing one way or the other, and the evidence of ‘the
people’ in the village interacting as a coherent group with the police
officers, there is nothing at all for an observer in our position to go on.
So picture the situation as it probably appeared to the police. Not
only did they face the tension in their position of any small force isolated in
a rural area, a tension shared to at least some extent by some police posts in
‘sophisticated and complex’ England. What could be described as a
criminally-incited, conspiratorial mob, engaged in vandalism and theft, might
rather be constitutionally-sanctioned customary authority in action. Or it might
be something in between, or something tending one way or the other. The law the
police are obliged to enforce allows actions which, with a subtle shift in fact
and (customary) law, it might also prohibit.
In other words the case could
just as easily be characterised
as a very complex, and extraordinarily
delicate, exercise of police discretion in law enforcement. Millhouse CJ was not
in a position to treat it as such only because the parties chose to leave the
matter opaque – which in itself suggests a degree of sensitivity and
subtlety in the officers’ task. It might well have been precisely the kind
of decision difficult to explain, let alone portray with proof, that
Hill
is meant to protect from illegitimate judicial second-guessing: decisions which,
in Lord Keith’s terms, ‘would not be regarded by the courts as
appropriate to be called into question’.
Indeed the sort of judicial
examination a full-blown negligence case would entail might be even less
appropriate in Kiribati than in any English incident, given the cultural gap
between the court and the islands. Even rendering the situation as perceived by
the parties into English would pose serious issues (compare the term
unimane, compelling an Anglophone reader’s attention to the
exoticism of its referent, with its English rendition, always used by
I-Kiribati:
the old men). A negligence trial, and a negligence verdict
and subsequent orders, could risk a significant chilling effect on the exercise
of discretion in policing. For an analogy picture, perhaps, the judicial review
in England, for purposes of a negligence claim by one of the parties, of a
rabbi’s resolution of a dispute about the governance of an Orthodox
synagogue, originally conducted in Hebrew: although, really, that would be far
closer to common-law culture than village-level Micronesian governance and its
relations with local police officers.
So treating such a case as simple
could, and in some cases must, amount to riding one form of Kiribati law –
the formal introduced criminal law – roughshod over another form of
Kiribati law – the vaguely constitutional indigenous law of governmental
authority. It would, to put it mildly, change the neighbourhood. And that would
risk the very inversion of another of Lord Atkin’s commandments in
Donoghue: that rulings on duties of care must be based on ‘a
general public sentiment of wrongdoing’.
Millhouse CJ is not lightly
to be taken as oblivious to all this. The point of his judgment seems to be that
evaluating that public sentiment in Kiribati, and resolving the abrasive
conflicts between customary authority and written criminal law, should be done
by the Kiribati legislature. In the meantime, if the police are content to
present their case bereft of real context, that is how the court will judge
it.
Good fences make good neighbours: the CA’s
decisionThe effect of the CA’s decision is to leave
Tio’s complaint, as a matter of Kiribati common law, within the village.
His choice-of-law conundrum is resolved: on facts like these, the common law
offers him no cause of action against the police. The involvement of the formal
state in the situation does not show in the common law. Apart from the
possibility of a legislated remedy, perhaps under the Constitution, he is left
to respond to the
unimane – by collecting on his default judgment
or otherwise.
This could be the point of the judgment too; or it might be
just an incident of an adoption of common-law rules, here concerning not the
immunity but the tests for a duty of care in negligence. By these tests, the
court holds, proximity is established either by the creation by the police of
the relevant risk or by their ‘voluntary assumption of
responsibility’. Manifestly the police here did not instigate the
vandalism and theft that injured Tio’s interests, and, in the CA’s
view, their knowledge of the impending attack, their propinquity, and their
contact with Tio did not constitute such an assumption.
But these are not
clearly plausible holdings. To create a risk must mean, in law, to contribute to
causing the risk to exist, and there was no evidence as to the effect of the
police inaction upon the villagers’ resolve to attack Tio’s
property. Even construed as omission – failure to advertise readiness to
interfere and failure to interfere – the role of the police could be taken
as causative; and their contact with the villagers, and conveying of the threat
to Tio, could equally well be construed as positive action.
Moreover, the
precedents cited do not all support the main proposition. In one,
Costello v
CC Northumbria [1999] 1 All ER 550 (CA), the defendant police
officer’s role in the injurious incident was, precisely, merely standing
by; that incident was an attack on the plaintiff officer by a third party
resisting the plaintiff, an incident which the defendant had done nothing at all
to bring about. More pointedly, there is a precedent conspicuously absent from
the CA’s selection:
Osman.
[21] It, too, was a
case of police inaction in the face of a risk they played no positive part in
creating. And the English CA’s holding in it was that proximity did exist,
due to the police officers’ extensive contacts with the plaintiffs and
their knowledge of the particular threat posed by the third party who eventually
shot the plaintiffs.
Osman is also a case illustrating the role of
assumption of responsibility, fairly clear on its facts, in contrast to another
Hill progeny,
Alexandrou. The CA in
AG v Tio held that
Alexandrou was the case among the English precedents which the Kiribati
case resembled. An automatic burglar alarm sounding at the police station
– the link between the parties in
Alexandrou – is thus like
the
Tio officers advising Tio that the villagers would be attacking his
house that night. This is already not intuitively obvious. But in
Alexandrou the police had responded, and checked the alarmed premises;
because they missed the signs of forced entry (carelessly, Alexandrou alleged)
they failed to prevent the subsequent burglary of which the plaintiff
complained. That is, they did not know the crime would occur; indeed they had
reason to believe, subjectively, that there was no particular likelihood of it
occurring. The Kiribati police were at the polar opposite of states of mind. The
English CA held that a mere alarm did not establish proximity. If knowledge of
the relevant risk is material to proximity, as of course it must be to
‘assumption of responsibility’, then the cases are contraries rather
than analogous.
Nonetheless,
Alexandrou did declare that the same
result would obtain where a member of the public called the police, and this
obiter dictum, if not the actual case, could apply analogously to
Tio. It depends on whether calling the police is sufficiently like the
police calling on you.
The tenuousness of these holdings emerges in the
light of the CA’s remark that the police conduct was ‘morally
indefensible.’ Now, the police actions in
Alexandrou, held to be a
case like Tio’s, could hardly be characterised as that. They were
careless, rather, as in most of the other cases cited by the Court of Appeal
where there was proximity:
Home Office v Dorset Yacht Co. [1970] AC 1004
(HL)(HO guards’ sleep allowing Borstal boys to escape via
plaintiffs’ yacht),
Rigby v CC Northamptonshire [1985] 2 All ER 985
(QB)(failure to have a fire truck standing by when teargas was used to drive an
armed madman out of the plaintiff’s shop),
Alcock v CC Yorkshire
[1992] AC 310 (crowd-control error causing deaths of plaintiffs’ relatives
in stadium stampede),
Knightley v Johns [1982] 1 All ER 851 (order to
drive wrong way along one-way road to block access to street).
Where one
can see moral wrong is in the cases of not only proximity but an
‘assumption of responsibility’ – assuring a family that the
madman harassing and threatening them will be arrested soon enough while failing
to arrest when evidence sufficed and it was clear that a physical attack was
likely (
Osman), failing to assist a fellow-officer being beaten by a
prisoner (
Costello, above), and, perhaps, leaving the personal file of an
informer loose on the seat of an empty police car (
Swinney v CC
Northumbria [1996] 3 All ER 449 (CA)).
Indeed in this
‘practical world’ where the Good Samaritan cannot reasonably be the
standard,
[2] it is difficult to see
how inaction
could be called morally indefensible in the absence of at
least ‘proximity’, if not the particular form of proximity called
‘voluntary assumption of responsibility’. Carelessness
per se
is measured objectively, and so has no moral significance; it is the duty it
violates, and particularly the relationship between the parties (which is what
‘proximity’ refers to, however vaguely) helping to create that duty,
which lends the lack of care a moral significance.
That the police in
Tio did not create the risk, if that is a reasonable view of the facts,
is not the barrier to proximity that the CA calls it, at least on the English
common law they rely on. And their moral judgment belies their legal conclusion,
given the fragility of the (only) analogy they drew. A satisfactory
interpretation of the decision must then return to its consequences, mentioned
above. It maintains a fence between the formal introduced law, here being
summoned through negligence doctrine, and customary political
authority.
Over Hill with Tio in the
PacificHowever narrow its basis in fact, Millhouse CJ’s
approach is quite sound as a qualification of
Hill. Indeed the
qualification is inherent in the
Hill doctrine, for it was precisely
Millhouse’s distinction that Lord Keith invoked as a ground for the
immunity on the
Hill facts.
The sort of police decision and action
whose ‘policy and discretion’ would be inappropriate for review by a
court was contrasted, by Keith, to ‘allegations of a simple and
straightforward type of failure – for example that a police officer
tripped and fell while pursuing a burglar’. The airing of police conduct,
and its subjection to judicial inspection, concerning
that sort of
allegation, he implies, would pose no issues of public policy.
It is the
difficulty of distinguishing such cases from the inappropriate ones, and
the exposure of matters inappropriate to litigation risked even by the drawing
of the distinction, which justifies the blanket approach adopted by
Hill.
(The allegations in
Hill itself, Keith held, were of the inappropriately
complex sort.)
That issue is avoided if a whole jurisdiction’s
policing activity may be characterised as overwhelmingly of the simple sort.
Where police detective and forensic work just does not include complex
investigations and bureaucratic procedures, and consists largely of following
simple rules to halt clear crime, apprehend known suspects, and preserve obvious
evidence, the prospect and experience of negligence litigation should have no
more undue chilling effect than it does on auto mechanics.
So the viability
of a ‘simple and straightforward’ exception to the
Hill
immunity depends on the viability of such a description of a
jurisdiction’s policing. In Kiribati and similar jurisdictions
that
depends on one’s view of what policing should be, for if the task is
simply the enforcement of the written law the work is indeed straightforward.
Crimes against the person and against tangible property are indeed clear, as a
rule, typically involving known individuals and obvious
evidence.
[23] Now, one can
identify other kinds of crime in such jurisdictions, and ways in which policing
could be more than enforcement of a criminal code whenever the police learn of
violations. Is the relative obscurity and difficulty of financial crime weighty
enough, and the possibly inscrutable informality of how some matters are left to
custom resolution legitimate enough, to reject the bifurcation of partial
immunity and partial exposure to liability, as the House of Lords rejected it?
Is the distinction between the simple tasks and the subtle ones difficult enough
to draw, or the drawing of it so likely to trench upon the matters properly left
free of judicial interference, that any doctrine relying on such a distinction
should be avoided, as the Lords held in
Hill?
These are issues to be
settled in the ‘Pacific Way’; we must hope they are not settled by
too easy an acceptance of the law of distant neighbours.
[*] [2003] KICA
10.
[**] [2003] KIHC
89.
[1] BA, LLB, BCL (McGill), LLM
(Dalhousie); Lecturer, School of Law, University of the South Pacific,
Vanuatu.
[2] Usually directly;
sometimes indirectly. In the case of Kiribati, the Constitution is silent as to
the law’s other sources; but the Laws of Kiribati Act 1989 (No 10
of 1989) directs the courts first to customary law, then to the common law of
Kiribati (ss. 4(2) and 6(3)), defining customary law as ‘customs and
usages, existing from time to time, of the natives of Kiribati’ (s.5(1))
and the common law as ‘the rules comprised in the common law, including
the doctrines of equity, of England (in this section referred to as “the
inherited rules”), as applied in the circumstances pertaining, from time
to time in Kiribati’ (s.6(1)). The English borrowing is subject to the
usual exclusion of rules that are ‘inapplicable or inappropriate’ to
Kiribati (s. 6(2)(b)).
[3] Hill
v Chief Constable of West Yorkshire [1989] AC 53 (HL), the ‘Yorkshire
Ripper’ case, holding that in addition to lack of proximity between a
police force and a class of potential victims of an unknown serial killer where
the class is ‘young women in Yorkshire’, a public-policy immunity
protects police forces generally from a negligence suit ‘of this
kind’ concerning their actions in ‘the investigation and suppression
of crime’.
[4] Alcock v
Chief Constable of South Yorkshire [1992] 1 AC 310 (HL); the Australian
rejection is in Tame v NSW (2002) 191 ALR 447 (HC).
[5] Arthur Hall v Simons
[2000] 3 All ER 673 (HL) and D’Orta-Ekenaike v Victoria Legal Aid
[2005] HCA 12 (HC) http://www.austlii.edu.au.
[6] The decisions are, in sequence
of issue: Wartaj Seafood Products v Min. Home Affairs & A-G [2000]
FJHC 100, Jagroop v Sokai & Tonga [2001] TOCA 10, Bachu & Wati
v Comm. Police & A-G [2004] FJCA 53, and Kumar v Comm. Police, Comm.
Prisons, & A-G [2005] FJCA 35 (all citations
http://paclii.org.vu/).
These are the case which could make up a line of
cases: see Fraser, ‘Police Negligence in the Pacific: Building a Case
around Hill (Case Comment on Kumar v Comm. Prisons, Comm. Police,
& A-G Fiji [2005] FJCA 35’, forthcoming, Commonwealth Law
Bulletin.
The clearest indications among them that Hill is adopted
are in the lone trial-level decision, Wartaj, and in Kumar (where,
however, it is offset confusingly, perhaps confusedly, by conflicting
dicta). These indications are obiter.
A few others would lie
outside the line. A Fiji plaintiff took a long shot some years ago, in Bokoci
(Takayawa Estate) v Kumar et al (Fiji Boxing Council) & A-G [1995] FJHC
143 (http://paclii.org.vu/), vainly alleging a police duty to look after the
contestants in licensed boxing matches. And there are Papua New Guinea cases
against the police, by members of the public and based on negligence, which do
not mention any immunity. But the facts these cases treat as
‘negligence’ are also batteries, indeed homicides, far from the
concerns of Hill or
Tio.
[7] In the same year
as Kumar in Fiji the NSW Court of Appeal, in Thompson & Thompson v
Vincent et al [2005] NSWCA 219, denied the claims but indicated bases on
which they might accept one: where there was assumption of responsibility
‘in a particular task’.
In Batchelor v State of Tasmania
[2005] TASSC 11 the Tasmanian Supreme Court allowed an action to proceed on the
basis that any immunity might not apply where the impugned police act was
contrary to the force’s own policies and instructions. And the court in
Batchelor leaves open the issue of whether Hill even applies in
Australia.
Earlier the NSWCA, in Cran v State of NSW [2004] NSWCA 92,
had characterised the argument from Hill as ‘the English
immunity’, and suggested (obiter) a police liability where the
plaintiff could show an assumption of responsibility – even where the
plaintiff is an accused person. (All citations
http://www.austlii.edu.au/).
[8]
In Waters v Comm. Police of the Met [2000] UKHL 50 the Lords denied a
strike-out application by a force sued by one of its officers for failure to
deal with bullying and intimidation by fellow officers. Responsibilities as an
employer displaced the immunity in matters not strictly amounting to ‘the
investigation and suppression of crime’. Lord Steyn for the majority
acknowledged that this was a development – an “increment” to
the law – and that it entailed adding to the consumption of police time
and resources. Lord Hutton, in a concurring opinion, simply held the Hill
policy concerns to be outweighed by the policy-based need to respond to such
shocking mismanagement of the Force.
In A-G v Hartwell [2004] UKPC 12
the Privy Council allowed a negligence action against the police of the British
Virgin Islands by a member of the public. Mr Hartwell was shot in a bar by a
police officer firing wildly at his ex-girlfriend, using the police revolver
assigned to the island where he was on duty. The Lords approved this suit
not on the basis of vicarious liability, but of direct negligence by the
force, in giving the officer unsupervised access to the firearm. This was said
to be a ‘positive act’, creating a risk, as opposed to the failure
to perform to a standard that is protected by the Hill doctrine.
In
Brooks v Comm. Police Met [2005] UKHL 24, the House of Lords approved the
Waters exceptions to the immunity – and took care to
dissociate itself from ‘the full breadth’ of the Hill
doctrine.
(All citations http://www.bailii.org/).
[9] The Lords in Brooks
noted that the advent of these rights’ incorporation into English law
weakened the basis of Hill. On 10 March this year, in Van Colle &
Van Colle v CC Hertfordshire Police [2006] EWHC 360 (QB)
http://www.bailii.org/ a trial judge effectively overruled the Hill
immunity, allowing what appears to be the first direct challenge to it by a
plaintiff relying on the Convention rights rather than the tort of
negligence.
[10] The absence of
cross-citation is not the product of literal ignorance, for the appellate
benches of these jurisdictions share judges: Tomkins JA sat on the Tio
and Jagroop panels (in Kiribati and Tonga), Pennington JA on Tio
and Bachu (in Kiribati and Fiji).
[11] As well as an occasional
insert from Canada or New Zealand. The HL and PC decisions mentioned above at
n.7, however, and the Australian ones at n.6, are not mentioned in the
Pacific cases.
[12] A cluster of Court of
Appeal decisions spawned by Hill reported in a single All England Report
a few years later. An automatic burglar alarm’s notification of the police
of trouble at the plaintiff’s store was not significantly different from
any emergency call to the police, and these made up far too numerous and
disparate a category of relations to constitute ‘proximity’:
Alexandrou v Oxford [1993] 4 All ER 328. The sighting by police officers
of a potential driving hazard on the road did not put them into
‘proximity’ with all other drivers who came upon the hazard later:
Ancell v McDermott [1993] 4 All ER 355.
In each case the availability
of the immunity was noted. Only in the third case, Osman v Ferguson
[1993] 4 All ER 344, did the facts compel the court actually to invoke it.
There, as in Hill, the injury was to the plaintiff was the criminal act
of a third party, a man known by the police to be a criminal at large –
but this time the police knew who he was, were practically and legally capable
of arresting him before the injury, knew that the plaintiff’s family were
his particular targets, and had, in addition to all that, explicitly advised the
family to rely on their efforts to deal with him. Proximity had to be found, and
was, so in Osman the policy immunity was the ratio decidendi for
dismissing the action. Osman has been ever since the ultimate example of
the immunity’s potency, given the sympathetic appeal of its facts.
The
Lords refused leave to appeal Osman, but the Osmans took their case to
the European Court of Human Rights, alleging a violation of their European
Convention on Human Rights right to access to justice: although the device of
striking-out a claim is necessarily implied by the common-law concept of duty as
a prerequisite of liability in negligence, it does mean the plaintiff’s
case is never heard on the merits, and the ECHR decided this was a denial of
judicial process: Osman v UK (1998) 5 BHRC 293. More to the present
point, it also decided that the Convention right to life imposed a positive
obligation upon police to assist people like the Osmans – the holding
inspiring Van Colle, above n.8.
[13] The opinion, like the
CA’s on appeal, is brief enough to omit paragraph citations.
[14] Beckstead v. Ottawa
(City) Chief of Police (1997) CanLII
1583 http://www.canlii.org/, (1997) 37 OR (3d) 62. The Canadian tort of
‘negligent police investigation’ was reconsidered, and approved, in
Hill v Hamilton-Wentworth Regional Police et al (2005) CanLII 34230
(Ontario CA), which is now on appeal to the Supreme Court: (2006) CanLII 13738
(SCC).
[15] So runs the test for novel
duties of care established by Caparo v Dickman [1990] 1 All ER 568 (HL).
It remains, in a rough way, the test in England, although it has been rejected
for Australia (Sullivan v Moody (2001) 75 ALJR 1570
(HC)).
[16] Above n.11.
[17] More precisely, the
‘assumption of responsibility’ creates a relationship between the
parties, the plaintiff relying on the defendant fulfilling the role it has
‘assumed’ (i.e. implicitly accepted), which one can describe as
‘proximity’ – and it displaces any judicial
consideration of whether the duty of care would be fair and reasonable, since,
after all, the defendant has already, ‘voluntarily’, accepted it.
This last gloss was made explicitly by Williams & Reed v Natural Life
& Mistlin [1998] 2 All ER 577
(HL).
[18] See, for example,
Jane’s Oceania Page (Dame Jane Resture) at
http://www.janeresture.com. She mentions:
....new social institutions also depend on their success on the village or
island authorities to ensure the usefulness in the community. In practice, the
determination of their identification and the embodiment with the community is
the prerogative of the unimane who will accord the appropriate sanctions. The
implementation of decisions by the latter rests finally with the younger
generations...
(http://www.janeresture.com/ki33/social_structure.htm)
[19]
The ‘six-o’clock order’: personal communication, I-Kiribati
student, USP School of Law (April 2006).
[20] For a case in Samoa similar
to Tio’s, in which the village council, or fono, resists liability,
see Leituala v Mauga [2004] WSSC 9 http://paclii.org.vu/. The statute is
the Village Fono Act 1990 (Samoa No 3, 1990).
[21] Above
n.11.[]
22 The law’s
world, as characterised in Lord Atkin’s discussion of the norm of loving
one’s neighbour, in Donoghue v Stevenson, leading to the passage
about those neighbours being the people one is affecting closely and directly
– answering ‘the lawyer’s question’ differently from
Luke 10:30-37, yet not quite so harshly as does the ‘assumption of
responsibility’
doctrine.
[23] This statement
could be qualified by noting that any dispute or violent incident in the Pacific
involving land title is not clear, as a legal issue.
In
Thompson & Thompson, above n.8, the defendant police were caught up
in a complex issue of land rights (about which plaintiff and another were
breaching the peace), and the NSW Court of Appeal took pains to emphasise that
police have no obligation to sort out ‘torts exam questions’ as part
of keeping the peace. They were reinforcing a distinction between criminal law
and land law that in the Pacific becomes willy-nilly one between introduced law
and customary law, land being generally held by customary title.